Article Type
Changed
Fri, 01/18/2019 - 11:17
Display Headline
Social Context Influences Creative Success

The success of a creation should, in theory, be determined by its creator, who is in the best position to determine how closely the creation matches the original vision. But in science, as in other creative endeavors, this is not the case. Success in science requires funding and publication, which does not arise from scientists’ opinions of their own work, but rather from the judgment rendered by a peer group comprising reviewers and editors.

This socially determined valuation of a creative effort helps to determine what society (or any social grouping) deems to be important. How much value we place on a new creation influences its creator’s drive to bridge the perceived gap between what is and what should be. The satiation of that creative drive is a biologically and psychologically relevant measure of creative success because it influences the likelihood that the creator will react again in the future to such perceived gaps, thus perpetuating creative behavior. Other factors may influence the degree of such satisfaction, including the reward received; the value that the creator’s culture places on individual attainment (Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2003;54:403-25); the creator’s enjoyment of the creative effort itself, as expressed in Mihály Csíkszentmihályi’s "Finding Flow: The Psychology of Engagement with Everyday Life" (New York: Basic Books, 1997); and the nature of the creation, in that creators who serve the greater good may derive a greater sense of happiness from their work, as discussed in Jonathan Haidt’s "The Happiness Hypothesis" (New York: Basic Books, 2006).

By Dr. Richard J. Caselli

Although the creator’s opinion is important, Dr. Csíkszentmihályi’s "systems model" of creativity highlights the role of society in which a gatekeeper determines what creative work will be admitted to the existing intended domain ("The Nature of Creativity: Current Psychological Perspectives" [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 325-39]). Because society cannot know the creator’s vision and so cannot match the creation to the vision, an external set of aesthetic rules is needed to judge creative achievement.

Aesthetics are the cooperatively determined hierarchical categorization and quantification of quality, expressed as rules or principles. Aesthetics reflect the opinions and values of the social grouping in which creativity arises. For example, the aesthetic value of a painting lies in the artist’s choice of color and form, and the aesthetic value of a scientific experiment lies in its methodological rigor, but the general principle of judging excellence is similar for both art and science.

How do we arrive at a set of aesthetic rules? Arguably, neurophysiology might lend some degree of objectivity. For example, neuronal receptive fields and firing patterns reflecting tonal quality, timbre, pitch, temporal structure, complexity, and familiarity of music can be measured (Nat. Neurosci. 2005;8:1241-7), but even so, there must be some determination of which responses or qualities are best. As a society, therefore, we must agree to a set of principles that define a work as being good or bad. Just as social norms define what conduct is expected and tolerated within a given society, aesthetics define what is desirable and undesirable within artistic, scientific, and other creative communities.

Leaders influence such norms, and within the social or professional grouping promote cooperation among its members to conform to the set standards (Nature 2003;422:137-40). Within large social groupings, cooperation can be and usually is enforced by the membership, either through designated experts or simply in the form of peer pressure.

Social norms are necessary because one person’s actions affect other members of the group. Evolutionary psychologists have provided evidence that our minds have evolved a social contract algorithm specialized for detecting liars, cheaters, and rule-breakers – those individuals who violate social law. Neuroeconomists suggest that social norms are based on "conditional cooperation," in which the level of cooperation of each group member is based on the level of mutual cooperation of all the members. If mutual cooperation is high, then individual cooperation is high. On the other hand, if I see many people breaking the law, benefiting as a result, and getting away with it, then I will be more likely to take a chance by breaking the law, too. Looting during times of social upheaval is a familiar manifestation of this principle.

For a paradigm, law, or any social norm to prevail, it must be enforced. And for the aesthetic principle to endure, social (aesthetic) norms must be enforced, and noncooperators (those who fail to comply with accepted aesthetic principles) punished, leaving their papers unpublished or grant applications unfunded.

As I mentioned in the February issue’s discussion about motivation, we like justice and we dislike injustice. Exacting social justice activates striatal and orbitofrontal reward substrates (Science 2004;305:1254-8), so we have powerful neurobiological drivers that serve to maintain social order.

 

 

However, social norms, aesthetic principles, and scientific paradigms can change. When the cost of cooperation with such a principle rises, due perhaps to mounting evidence that the scientific paradigm is wrong, the level of mutual cooperation will drop. Recall that if the reward value of an ongoing action drops, the reduced reward is the signal that drives the formation of a new action plan. When mutual cooperation with a social norm drops and defection rates rise, the social norm is destined to break down. In science, this is termed a "paradigm shift," as described by Thomas S. Kuhn in "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970).

Aesthetic laws, as practiced at the peer-to-peer and leadership levels, define and validate the merit of a creation. Aesthetic rules, when they are enforced by credible authorities, become accepted fact. We may even extend this principle to another human creation – morality – and we shall do so next month.

This column, "Evoked Potentials," regularly appears in Clinical Neurology News, an Elsevier publication. Dr. Caselli is the medical editor of Clinical Neurology News and is a professor of neurology at the Mayo Clinic in Scottsdale, Ariz.

Author and Disclosure Information

Publications
Legacy Keywords
peer revies, creative efforts, society, norms
Sections
Author and Disclosure Information

Author and Disclosure Information

The success of a creation should, in theory, be determined by its creator, who is in the best position to determine how closely the creation matches the original vision. But in science, as in other creative endeavors, this is not the case. Success in science requires funding and publication, which does not arise from scientists’ opinions of their own work, but rather from the judgment rendered by a peer group comprising reviewers and editors.

This socially determined valuation of a creative effort helps to determine what society (or any social grouping) deems to be important. How much value we place on a new creation influences its creator’s drive to bridge the perceived gap between what is and what should be. The satiation of that creative drive is a biologically and psychologically relevant measure of creative success because it influences the likelihood that the creator will react again in the future to such perceived gaps, thus perpetuating creative behavior. Other factors may influence the degree of such satisfaction, including the reward received; the value that the creator’s culture places on individual attainment (Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2003;54:403-25); the creator’s enjoyment of the creative effort itself, as expressed in Mihály Csíkszentmihályi’s "Finding Flow: The Psychology of Engagement with Everyday Life" (New York: Basic Books, 1997); and the nature of the creation, in that creators who serve the greater good may derive a greater sense of happiness from their work, as discussed in Jonathan Haidt’s "The Happiness Hypothesis" (New York: Basic Books, 2006).

By Dr. Richard J. Caselli

Although the creator’s opinion is important, Dr. Csíkszentmihályi’s "systems model" of creativity highlights the role of society in which a gatekeeper determines what creative work will be admitted to the existing intended domain ("The Nature of Creativity: Current Psychological Perspectives" [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 325-39]). Because society cannot know the creator’s vision and so cannot match the creation to the vision, an external set of aesthetic rules is needed to judge creative achievement.

Aesthetics are the cooperatively determined hierarchical categorization and quantification of quality, expressed as rules or principles. Aesthetics reflect the opinions and values of the social grouping in which creativity arises. For example, the aesthetic value of a painting lies in the artist’s choice of color and form, and the aesthetic value of a scientific experiment lies in its methodological rigor, but the general principle of judging excellence is similar for both art and science.

How do we arrive at a set of aesthetic rules? Arguably, neurophysiology might lend some degree of objectivity. For example, neuronal receptive fields and firing patterns reflecting tonal quality, timbre, pitch, temporal structure, complexity, and familiarity of music can be measured (Nat. Neurosci. 2005;8:1241-7), but even so, there must be some determination of which responses or qualities are best. As a society, therefore, we must agree to a set of principles that define a work as being good or bad. Just as social norms define what conduct is expected and tolerated within a given society, aesthetics define what is desirable and undesirable within artistic, scientific, and other creative communities.

Leaders influence such norms, and within the social or professional grouping promote cooperation among its members to conform to the set standards (Nature 2003;422:137-40). Within large social groupings, cooperation can be and usually is enforced by the membership, either through designated experts or simply in the form of peer pressure.

Social norms are necessary because one person’s actions affect other members of the group. Evolutionary psychologists have provided evidence that our minds have evolved a social contract algorithm specialized for detecting liars, cheaters, and rule-breakers – those individuals who violate social law. Neuroeconomists suggest that social norms are based on "conditional cooperation," in which the level of cooperation of each group member is based on the level of mutual cooperation of all the members. If mutual cooperation is high, then individual cooperation is high. On the other hand, if I see many people breaking the law, benefiting as a result, and getting away with it, then I will be more likely to take a chance by breaking the law, too. Looting during times of social upheaval is a familiar manifestation of this principle.

For a paradigm, law, or any social norm to prevail, it must be enforced. And for the aesthetic principle to endure, social (aesthetic) norms must be enforced, and noncooperators (those who fail to comply with accepted aesthetic principles) punished, leaving their papers unpublished or grant applications unfunded.

As I mentioned in the February issue’s discussion about motivation, we like justice and we dislike injustice. Exacting social justice activates striatal and orbitofrontal reward substrates (Science 2004;305:1254-8), so we have powerful neurobiological drivers that serve to maintain social order.

 

 

However, social norms, aesthetic principles, and scientific paradigms can change. When the cost of cooperation with such a principle rises, due perhaps to mounting evidence that the scientific paradigm is wrong, the level of mutual cooperation will drop. Recall that if the reward value of an ongoing action drops, the reduced reward is the signal that drives the formation of a new action plan. When mutual cooperation with a social norm drops and defection rates rise, the social norm is destined to break down. In science, this is termed a "paradigm shift," as described by Thomas S. Kuhn in "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970).

Aesthetic laws, as practiced at the peer-to-peer and leadership levels, define and validate the merit of a creation. Aesthetic rules, when they are enforced by credible authorities, become accepted fact. We may even extend this principle to another human creation – morality – and we shall do so next month.

This column, "Evoked Potentials," regularly appears in Clinical Neurology News, an Elsevier publication. Dr. Caselli is the medical editor of Clinical Neurology News and is a professor of neurology at the Mayo Clinic in Scottsdale, Ariz.

The success of a creation should, in theory, be determined by its creator, who is in the best position to determine how closely the creation matches the original vision. But in science, as in other creative endeavors, this is not the case. Success in science requires funding and publication, which does not arise from scientists’ opinions of their own work, but rather from the judgment rendered by a peer group comprising reviewers and editors.

This socially determined valuation of a creative effort helps to determine what society (or any social grouping) deems to be important. How much value we place on a new creation influences its creator’s drive to bridge the perceived gap between what is and what should be. The satiation of that creative drive is a biologically and psychologically relevant measure of creative success because it influences the likelihood that the creator will react again in the future to such perceived gaps, thus perpetuating creative behavior. Other factors may influence the degree of such satisfaction, including the reward received; the value that the creator’s culture places on individual attainment (Annu. Rev. Psychol. 2003;54:403-25); the creator’s enjoyment of the creative effort itself, as expressed in Mihály Csíkszentmihályi’s "Finding Flow: The Psychology of Engagement with Everyday Life" (New York: Basic Books, 1997); and the nature of the creation, in that creators who serve the greater good may derive a greater sense of happiness from their work, as discussed in Jonathan Haidt’s "The Happiness Hypothesis" (New York: Basic Books, 2006).

By Dr. Richard J. Caselli

Although the creator’s opinion is important, Dr. Csíkszentmihályi’s "systems model" of creativity highlights the role of society in which a gatekeeper determines what creative work will be admitted to the existing intended domain ("The Nature of Creativity: Current Psychological Perspectives" [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988, p. 325-39]). Because society cannot know the creator’s vision and so cannot match the creation to the vision, an external set of aesthetic rules is needed to judge creative achievement.

Aesthetics are the cooperatively determined hierarchical categorization and quantification of quality, expressed as rules or principles. Aesthetics reflect the opinions and values of the social grouping in which creativity arises. For example, the aesthetic value of a painting lies in the artist’s choice of color and form, and the aesthetic value of a scientific experiment lies in its methodological rigor, but the general principle of judging excellence is similar for both art and science.

How do we arrive at a set of aesthetic rules? Arguably, neurophysiology might lend some degree of objectivity. For example, neuronal receptive fields and firing patterns reflecting tonal quality, timbre, pitch, temporal structure, complexity, and familiarity of music can be measured (Nat. Neurosci. 2005;8:1241-7), but even so, there must be some determination of which responses or qualities are best. As a society, therefore, we must agree to a set of principles that define a work as being good or bad. Just as social norms define what conduct is expected and tolerated within a given society, aesthetics define what is desirable and undesirable within artistic, scientific, and other creative communities.

Leaders influence such norms, and within the social or professional grouping promote cooperation among its members to conform to the set standards (Nature 2003;422:137-40). Within large social groupings, cooperation can be and usually is enforced by the membership, either through designated experts or simply in the form of peer pressure.

Social norms are necessary because one person’s actions affect other members of the group. Evolutionary psychologists have provided evidence that our minds have evolved a social contract algorithm specialized for detecting liars, cheaters, and rule-breakers – those individuals who violate social law. Neuroeconomists suggest that social norms are based on "conditional cooperation," in which the level of cooperation of each group member is based on the level of mutual cooperation of all the members. If mutual cooperation is high, then individual cooperation is high. On the other hand, if I see many people breaking the law, benefiting as a result, and getting away with it, then I will be more likely to take a chance by breaking the law, too. Looting during times of social upheaval is a familiar manifestation of this principle.

For a paradigm, law, or any social norm to prevail, it must be enforced. And for the aesthetic principle to endure, social (aesthetic) norms must be enforced, and noncooperators (those who fail to comply with accepted aesthetic principles) punished, leaving their papers unpublished or grant applications unfunded.

As I mentioned in the February issue’s discussion about motivation, we like justice and we dislike injustice. Exacting social justice activates striatal and orbitofrontal reward substrates (Science 2004;305:1254-8), so we have powerful neurobiological drivers that serve to maintain social order.

 

 

However, social norms, aesthetic principles, and scientific paradigms can change. When the cost of cooperation with such a principle rises, due perhaps to mounting evidence that the scientific paradigm is wrong, the level of mutual cooperation will drop. Recall that if the reward value of an ongoing action drops, the reduced reward is the signal that drives the formation of a new action plan. When mutual cooperation with a social norm drops and defection rates rise, the social norm is destined to break down. In science, this is termed a "paradigm shift," as described by Thomas S. Kuhn in "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970).

Aesthetic laws, as practiced at the peer-to-peer and leadership levels, define and validate the merit of a creation. Aesthetic rules, when they are enforced by credible authorities, become accepted fact. We may even extend this principle to another human creation – morality – and we shall do so next month.

This column, "Evoked Potentials," regularly appears in Clinical Neurology News, an Elsevier publication. Dr. Caselli is the medical editor of Clinical Neurology News and is a professor of neurology at the Mayo Clinic in Scottsdale, Ariz.

Publications
Publications
Article Type
Display Headline
Social Context Influences Creative Success
Display Headline
Social Context Influences Creative Success
Legacy Keywords
peer revies, creative efforts, society, norms
Legacy Keywords
peer revies, creative efforts, society, norms
Sections
Article Source

PURLs Copyright

Inside the Article